In the Enciclopedia Libre Universal
en Español, on the Internet, one can find an outline of an article about Johann
Gottlieb Fichte, written by an anonymous author, which, as I was reading it,
reminded me of things that seemed to have been taken as notes to my classes
about History of Contemporary Philosophy at the University of Oviedo (Spain).
It is only an outline with mistakes, inaccuracies, lack of connection in the
order followed, etc. For this reason, I have decided to complete it and give it
a more finished form. I do this because I am especially interested in Fichte,
because he puts the operatory activity as the origin of our rational knowledge and
because he is one of the most distorted and worst understood great German
classic philosophers, who still awaits today for someone who will show him to
us in his true depth and present philosophical importance. Moreover, a summary
of his philosophy may serve as an appetizer in the face of the 200 anniversary
of his death, which take place this year. The outline of the Encyclopedia would
read as follows:
It is well-known the great
influence that Marxism had during the twentieth century. Marx was in his
intellectual origins a left Hegelian. For this reason Hegel was very important
to understand Marxism and he was deeply studied, for he was seen as the one who
brought to completion the philosophy initiated by Kant. The philosophers who
were in the middle, Maimon, Reinhold, Fichte and Schelling, were seen, however,
as mere intermediary links. But this in not so, at least in the case of Fichte
and Schelling. They are something more than that, although still today they are
far from achieving a fair treatment with respect to Kant and Hegel, both
broadly recognized as great giants of modern thought.
Notwithstanding, Hegel's star
seems to decline with the fall of the Berlin Wall and the failure of the
socialist experiment that seemed to be more influential. A Hegel that, it
cannot be forgotten, also influenced the fascist movement. Because, although
the fascist theories opposed the marxists, there is also in their base an
interpretation of the Hegelian theories. On the other hand, it looks like
Schelling's criticism made in his Munich and Berlin lectures against Hegelian
philosophy starts to be taken seriously.
However, we will focus in what
follows in the figure of J. Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1814). He is presented as a
passionate follower of Kant, whom he went to visit in Könisberg, walking from
Poland, and asked for help, given his precarious financial status. Kant offered
him to publish, under his recommendation, his essay Attempt at a Critique of
All Revelation, which would make him famous as a young writer. Nevertheless,
good old Kant would publish an article rejecting Fichte's philosophy as not
continuing his, by the time already famous, critical philosophy. Furthermore,
this happened at a very critical time in Fichte's live, when he was accused of
atheism and was forced to resign his chair in the University of Jena. He had
been promoted there by Goethe, at the time minister of Culture in the Duchy of
Weimar, on which the university depended. Goethe wanted to put the University
of Jena at the forefront of German culture and promoted the access to its
chairs to Schelling and Hegel, who will be the great philosophical stars after
Fichte's stunning five years (1794-1799) in Jena.
Fichte's
philosophy starts from Kant, but developing ideas of its own. Something similar
to what happened to Malebranche and Spinoza with Descartes. Although Fichte
doesn't accept the background of Spinoza's philosophy, his work is very
influenced by him. Spinoza was famous for being an atheist and a pantheist,
which motivated the interested of the youth of the time in his work, although
Spinoza had been treated in the eighteenth century, in Lessing's words, as a
“dead dog” and all sort of refutations of his work had been developed. However,
he was saved as a great philosopher by Lessing himself in an interview
posthumously published by Jacobi, which produced a great controversy and
scandal (See Manuel F. Lorenzo, "La polémica sobre el espinosismo de Lessing", El
Basilisco nº 1, 1989, pp.65-74), attracting the interest in his famous
Ethic among the young Germans.
Fichte was one
of those youngster that read and studied with great interest Spinoza's work. He
read it critically, for, after Kant's “Copernican Revolution”, it is only
possible a critical philosophy that does not admit knowledge of “things in
themselves”, as Spinoza's God Substance was, located beyond all human
experience, real or possible. However, Fichte consider that Spinoza offered the
best model of a good foundation for Cartesian philosophy and took his ideas to
a deeper and more coherent expression. For Fichte Kant's philosophy was also
not well founded, because it offers new answers, but it departs from obscure
premises. There are in Kant some contradictions, as Jacobi had pointed out.
According to Kant, only in the phenomenal world is it legitimate to talk about
causality. Nevertheless, as he explains the theory of knowledge, he considers
that there is a matter of knowledge (sensations) that are manifestations of the
“thing in itself” which is behind and beyond the phenomena. That is, for Kant
something noumenal, the Thing in Itself, is the cause of phenomenal sensations,
applying thus improperly the causality, which can only be applied to the
relations among phenomena, to the relations among the unknowable noumenal world
and the phenomenal.
Moreover, the
unity of the famous three Kantian Critiques is a false unity by juxtaposition
based in Tetens' theory of the three psychological faculties. Fichte intends to
find a unity in Kantian philosophy in a strictly philosophical manner,
rationally coherent and complete.
However the
reformulation of Kantism leads him to a choice between two Ideas which preside
in Kant the division of reality in two worlds: the phenomenal and the noumenal.
The Idea of the I (Transcendental Ego) and that of the Thing in Itself.
If we depart, as the primary Idea, from the Thing in Itself we fall into a
pre-critical philosophy similar to Spinozism. But if we depart from the I we
can reconstruct the World in a critical and limited way, as the world of
phenomena. Not as a world in itself, but rather as the world such as it appears
in the representation (Vorstellung) that we make of it. Furthermore,
Fichte reenforces this choice with the claim that concerning philosophical
issues we cannot remain neutral, but rather we must choose the philosophy that
is in accordance with the type of person we are. In that case, those who
advocate for that everything remains as it is, for fatalism, will choose a
dogmatic philosophy based in the permanent and eternal Substance from which
everything comes with necessity, being pointless to rebel. However, those who
advocate for liberty and change, will choose to depart from the operative
liberty which is attributed to the I, facing a world that can be changed.
Fichte chose the I. In such a sense, Fichte's philosophical position was viewed
sympathetically by the advocates of the French Revolution, which had taken
place at the time, and view with suspicion by the politically reactionary
positions, which gave him an aura of audacious thinker surrounded all his live
by controversy.
Fichte
substitutes, then, Spinoza's Substance, the God-creative Nature, for the human
I. The I now take the relative place occupied before by the divine substance in
Spinoza, but this does not mean that Fichte understands the I as a spiritual
Substance, in the manner of the Cartesian cogito, but rather he
understands it as action, as operatory activity (Tathandlung), from
which it is derived, not anymore the World, but rather our representations of
the World. Such an I, which Fichte calls the Absolute I, is not anymore the
psychological or empirical I, but rather the Kantian Transcendental I that
encompasses all my representations and has the task of making the synthesis of
intuitions and concepts according to schemes of the creative imagination. The
world, not in itself, but such as it appears to us, is then
constructed-constituted by human subjects themselves.
Fichte performs
an “ontological turn” which complements Kant's gnoseological “Copernican turn”.
And he does this inverting Spinoza. Because, Kant, besides excelling above all
in analytical genius, as Fichte himself recognized when he compared him with
Reinhold's synthesizing “genius”, was not particularly impressed by Spinoza's
philosophy, whom he had not read or studied directly, according to his own
confession, and he knew about him above all through indirect references. The
young Fichte, however, was attracted by the famous controversy about
“Spinozism” and Lessing. That which attracts Fichte about Spinoza is the
rigorous and precise form of ordering more geometrico his philosophy. In
such a sense, Fichte will try to order the content of the new Kantian
philosophy, inclined still towards the baroque aristotelic-scholastic molds
that had been renovated in the Germanic philosophical world by Christian Wolff,
in a non scholastic form of exposition and development. A form which was more
in accordance with the new way of systematic founding and exposition introduced
by Descartes, with his hypothetical-deductive model from the cogito as a
fundamentum inconcusum, to extract from it, in the form of rigorously
demonstrated propositions, as Spinoza did, the new philosophical contents
resulting from Kantian criticism. In turn, the geometrical deduction will be
substituted by the new dialectical deduction that Kant had introduced in his
Critiques in order to escape from the antinomies and contradictions to which
the superficial Cartesian rationalism lead.
Under these
cirsumstances the “ontological turn” that Fichte introduces will consist in
substituting the Spinozist Substance by the Kantian transcendental I. The task
of a critical philosophy will not be anymore, as in the Spinozist metaphysic,
to deduct the entire reality from the Deus sive Natura, but rather
philosophy must abandon such metaphysical reveries in order to undertake tasks
that are more humble, but more humanly achievable, such as departing from human
consciousness in order to try to deduce, not anymore the world as it is in
itself, but rather how it is for us, the world as representation (Vorstellung).
In this Fichte continued the steps of Reinhold, who he succeeded in the chair
of Jena, although having to essentially modify the so-called Principle of
Consciousness (Satz des Bewusstsein) that was understood by Reinhold as
an nondeductible Fact (Tatsache), being ingeniously interpreted by
Fichte as an Action (Tathandlung). Neither the Kantian Thing in itself,
which Reinhold had brilliantly discarded, nor the Reinhold's “facts of
consciousness”, are the origin of human knowledge. Rather, for Fichte, only the
actions of the I are the origin of human knowledge. Action is the essence of
the I in the specific sense that action is not understood as another property
of the I among others, but rather that the I is itself essentially activity,
and for that reason his philosophy is a philosophy of action, a sort of
pragmatism avant la letter that overcomes the Cartesian-Kantian
dualism, because the I itself derives, constitutes itself and constitutes the
world through his actions. This way, Fichte is the first of the great
philosophers which tries to explain human knowledge, not from the mere
sensations or innate Ideas, but rather from the actions of the human subject
itself, in a sense which will be taken up again by Jean Piaget in his famous
Genetic Epistemology.
Fichte tries to reconstruct
systematically Kant's work departing from the Transcendental Ego as a
critical foundation of which we can have experience, a cognitive experience of
a psychological or “mental” origin. He imitates Spinoza when he tries certain
logical formalization of such cognitive experience through logical-deductive
principles. But such Principles are not fixed metaphysically. They must be
extracted from experience, from what happens when we know something. Fichte
asked his students to look at the wall and to analyze what happens in such
perceptive act: an I who perceives a Not-I. Then he asked them to remember such
act. In the remembrance a new I appears who perceives himself in the moment in
which he was looking at the wall. This new I is a reflexive I in which the
subject unfolds himself and puts himself as an object. Even if we continue to
introduce new acts of knowledge as that of an I who remembered that he was
looking at the wall, and so forth, an I different from the reflexive I will not
appear. For this reason the first principle of Fichte's philosophy is “the I
puts the I”. Said in a Cartesian way: I reflect, therefore I exist. The I
produces or generates the I itself, consciousness produces consciousness. This
way the first principle of Fichte's philosophy is the reflexive identity:
I = I (First Principle)
However, the I does not produce
consciousness from himself, as if it were a spiritual Substance or a divine
Spirit, as in Berkeley, but rather, something needs to be presupposed that
forces him to do so. For this reason, a resistance presents itself against the
I in his actions, an unknown “Thing in itself” which already appears in the
perceptive I as the “wall” and that Fichte prefers to call Not-I, for we cannot
know positively what it is. In fact, according to Fichte, the positing of a
Not-I derives, not from knowledge, as in Kant, but rather, it is a belief which
derives from a feeling of encountering something that resists our actions. This
way he introduces a sort of “infinite Substance” as something a posteriori,
unlike Spinoza who departs from it. Therefore, the second principle of Fichte's
philosophy is: “the Not-I opposes the I”:
(I/NOT-I) (Second Principle).
The I is threatened by the thing
in itself, by the Not-I, in the same way as the Island of Reason, which Kant
talked about, was threatened by mysterious oceans of unknown limits. We cannot
know the Not-I and the only thing that we can say about it is that it is not
the I.
However, the ceaseless activity
of the I would not make sense confronted with an indivisible, infinite and
unembraceable Not-I, as the “thing in itself” of the old metaphysics. For this
reason it is necessary, in the Kantian sense, to restrict knowledge to the
faith world of the phenomena given to consciousness. Hence Fichte introduces a
“postulate of limitation”, understanding that the opposition between the I and
the Not-I only has sense when it is given within the I, between a divisible I
and an indivisible Not-I. The contradiction between the I and the Not-I cannot
be considered in a general and indeterminate manner, for it would be a
contradiction between two infinities. The opposition I and Not-I must be
limited and given in the I. According to this the Third Principle is: “in the I
a divisible I opposes an indivisible Not-I”:
I(I/NOT-I) (Third Principle).
From
his Third Principle Fichte reorganizes the whole Kantian philosophy. Fichte
tries to reconstruct from this Third Principle all the representations of
consciousness, whether theoretical or practical. This way the Third Principle
I(I/NOT-I) can be interpreted in two ways: if we suppose the Not-I as acting
over the passive I we obtain the representations of theoretical knowledge that
Kant analyzes in the Critique of Pure Reason. If, on the contrary, we
suppose an active I acting over a Not-I which presents a passive resistance to
it, we obtain the moral representations, or practical in general, analyzed by
Kant in his other two critiques.
REAL
SERIES: I (NOT-I → I)
IDEAL
SERIES: I (I → NOT-I)
The
Real Series of necessary representations focuses on how sensation, perception,
imagination, concepts, etc. are produced. The Ideal Series of practical
representations has to do with the genesis of ethical, moral, political,
juridical, etc., representations.
These
are Fichte's rational principles of subjectivity that remain constant
throughout his work, the famous Three Principles of his Doctrine of Science (Wissenschaftslehre)
laid out in 1794. With them he intends to explain rationally the totality of
human knowledge, both our theoretical cognitive representations and our
practical, organizing systematically the novel results that Kant had reached in
his famous three Critiques, but not in a monist way, as Reinhold intended with
his famous Principle of Consciousness (Satz des Bewusstsein), but
through a dialectical construction of Three Principles that “close” or narrow
the field of human knowledge in a way that we could compare to Structures of
rational explanatory principles, such as, for example, the famous Three
Principles of Newtonian Mechanics, in which, from the same principles a set of theorems
are proven. Fichte, imitating Spinoza, will conceive of the proven truths of
his Philosophy as Theorems, although these proofs don't follow the geometric
mode, but the dialectic of the thesis, antithesis and synthesis which Kant had
begun.
However,
Fichte's three principles are not a merely logical-formal deduction, but a
reproduction of the dialectical development of human knowledge itself which is
evident when we observe the structure outlined by the Three Principles, interpreting
the First as a Thesis or starting opposition (I=I); the second as a negation of
such thesis (I/Not-I); the Third as a result of the Synthesis of both:
I(I/Not-I).
For
this reason, the most adequate method for philosophy, according to Fichte, is
the dialectical method. Fichte sees philosophy as a constructive and synthetic
activity which advances, with the application in all its territories of the
dialectical method; although he introduces a form of founding idealist
philosophy and more related to an anthropological foundation than to an
ontological, his work is entirely original and novel. His brilliant use of the
dialectical method against the analytic will end up influencing, through Hegel,
Marxism, who will popularize it. The importance of the dialectical method
manifests itself in that, for Fichte, “philosophy is not only a system of
thought, a mere collection or connexion of Propositions (Sammlung von Sätzen)
that can be learned, but rather, a view of things (Ansicht der Dinge), a
special mode of thought (Denkart), a dialectical mode of thought, that
we can reproduce in ourselves” (J. T. Fichte, Wissenschaftslehre nova método,
Felix MeinerVerlag, Hamburg, 1994, p. 11). This way he picks up the well known
Kantian distinction between knowing philosophy and knowing how to philosophize.
Fichte
applied the principles of his Theory of Science (Wissenschaftslehre) to
his political theory (The closed commercial State), to his moral
philosophy (Ethics), to law (Foundation of natural Right), but
not to nature. This will be done by his brilliant young follower in Jena,
Schelling, but giving birth to a very different philosophy to the Fichtean,
just as Hegel remarked in his work The
Difference Between Fichte's and Schelling's System of Philosophy (1801).
As
much as Fichte rejects Spinoza's philosophy as a pre-critical philosophy,
nevertheless, his agrees with him in the defense of freedom of thought: the
State must allow all rational opinions. The tradition of modern democratic
ideas is born with Spinoza, with his opposition to the religious and political
fanaticism of his time. Although Spinoza was a famous and influencing figure
during his short life, he was later outcast and treated as a “dead dog” because
of his radicalness and heterodoxy. Fichte also wrote an Ethics,
according to the principles of his Doctrine of Science. There he follows Kant's
critique to “material ethics” that would put pleasure or happiness in this life
as a reward for virtue. Kant puts virtue and not happiness at the centre, following
this way the stoic tradition which claims that the reward to virtue can only be
virtue itself. This way a “formal ethics” is defined which demands following
the Categorical Imperative of moral law requires doing the good without getting
any material reward in exchange. But Kant also considers that the highest good
should include Happiness and not only Virtue. He sees in the Christian belief
in the reward in the afterlife, in the life of the pure noumenal world of
resurrected spirits, a compensation, not material (phenomenal) but purely
spiritual (noumenal), for those who follow the virtuous life. According to
Fichte this is a relapse in a naïve Christianity that presupposes a God who can
be bought with diligence, etc. For him, happiness or the blessed life (The
Way Towards the Blessed Life, 1806) is the satisfaction of duty well done.
This way the reward is neither material nor formal: it is the pure feeling of
satisfaction that is based not in pleasing a personal God understood as a judge
of rewards and punishments, but rather, in a feeling of Love towards a God who
is nothing different from the Moral Order of the World, with whom Humanity has
to identify itself in is continuous improvement process and rational progress.
Such an Idea of a purely rational God was introduced by Fichte in order to
scape from the accusation of atheism made against him and which caused, under
strong pressures, his proudly voluntary resignation and cessation, - not
“expulsion” as it is usually said -, from the University of Jena.
It is
true that since the strong Kantian critiques to the Proofs of the Existence of
God, a kind of split between Philosophy and Theology starts, but the then
prevailing political positions and the religious mentality in the Germanic
world, in contrast to the French, for example, prevented the development of a
philosophy exempt of theology. Shelling and Hegel learned from the religious
attacks that Fichte had suffered and for this reason they use in their works an
ambiguous onto-theological language with the aim of avoiding conflicts with the
religious communities, both protestant and catholic, by which the Germans still
remained divided. But the reason for the greater importance of religion in
Fichte's work after his period in Jena also has its motives in weaknesses in
his own philosophy. It is true that Fichte doesn't use the analysis of the I as
a mere founding Cartesian springboard which still needs to lift itself to a
theological instance, to the existence of a rational and good God who warrants
the evidences of the I, but it is rather the case that, after the Kantian
demolition of the so-called “ontological argument” of the existence of God,
which Descartes still accepted, Fichte proposes a dialectical and internal
foundation to the I's own world, similar to what Husserl will call an Egology,
maybe in opposition to Theology. That is, the logical reconstruction of
Subjectivity and the world of objects as cognitive representations according to
purely philosophical-rational principles.
Nevertheless,
when Fichte tries to reconstruct the world of the alter egos, of
intersubjectivity, through the category of “recognition” (Anerkennung) –
taken and later made famous by Hegel in his well-known “Dialectic of Master and
Slave” in the Phenomenology of Spirit -, he is forced to appeal, as a
warrant of the triumph of good, to the existence of a God understood, through
Kantian influence, as the “moral order” of the world. The recognition between
two Is is not direct, for through it I only perceive the other I as my representation,
not in itself. I can only reach his reality in an indirect manner, through God
himself who is the warrant of the existence of a Moral Order which includes
other persons like me necessary in order to accomplish it. For this reason,
there is in Fichte a sort of Malebranchean Occasionalism in so far as persons
only recognize themselves as such not directly, but through the identification
with the mentioned divine Order. In The Destination of Man (1800), he
writes: “It doesn't flow directly from you to me and from me to you the
knowledge that we have one from the other; we are separated by a limitative
insuperable ordering. Only through our common spiritual source we know
respectively the one of the other; only in it we know and influence mutually” (II,
301). Compared to the Malebranch introducer, developing Cartesian Ideas, of the
existence of an “intelligible physical space”, Fichte is the introducer,
developing Kantian Ideas, of an “intelligible moral order”, built from the
operatory activities of the individual Is, and not by mere divine revelation,
although still warranted by theological assumptions. Such a Moral Order,
imposed over the particular wills, will be the guiding Idea which will open the
way to the so-called Social Sciences through the Hegelian Idea of the Objective
Spirit and that Marx will reinterpret as a mystification of positive historical
realities such as the economical struggles causing the structural laws which
impose themselves “over the will” of men, or in the functionalist and
structuralist Anthropology, as elementary structures of kinship, etc.
With
all this the Fichtean Philosophy of the time of Berlin is marked by a
theological dependence, even acquiring a mystical tone in his writing The
Way Towards the Blessed Life (1806), which has contributed to the
contraposition between the revolutionary Fichte of Jena and the religious and
conservative Fichte of Berlin. Nevertheless, it can be admitted that there is a
basic continuity, a nuclear structure or common knot, between all the different
and numerous versions of his Doctrine of Science. In such sense, Fichte never
abandoned his Doctrine of the Three Principles which made him famous in Jena.
It could be said then, that as well as Descartes would have been the precursor
of the Kant's “Copernican Turn” when starting with such good step, as the poet
Peguy would say, from the “I think”, although understanding such I as a
substance which requires the participation and warranty in its evidences of the
infinite divine Substance, Fichte is the precursor of the comprehension of
theoretical knowledge as a knowledge that is constructed and is founded in
practical knowledge, just as, for instance, Piaget's Epistemology will claim
(see my article “Fichte a la luz de Piaget”), but he was unable to find a
foundation of moral knowledge without appealing to theological beliefs.
Regarding
his political doctrines, Fichte considers that economical Liberalism, by
itself, cannot end with misery or economical crisis, and he proposes, in The
Closed Commercial State (1800), the intervention of the State in the
Economy. The State cannot allow the free exchange of goods, in the same way as
it doesn't allow the free circulation of individuals, but rather it must
intervene controlling their production and flux, with the end of avoiding
economical crisis. The citizens are defined by the property they acquire with
their job, but such property must not be understood in the substantialist way
of Locke, or Kant, for example, of a thing possessed, but rather of something
only necessary in accordance to the capacity or operatory activity of he who
possesses it. Fichte, unlike Kant, doesn't accept the death penalty as an
unilateral right of the State. For when the citizen accepts the Social Contract
on which the State is based, he cannot renounce to an non-renounceable right,
the right to live, putting his life on the hands of the State. Against a Kant
who is a convinced supporter of the death penalty, Fichte claims that the
penalty is not an end in itself, only a mean to reintegrate the individual in
society, reestablishing the reciprocal acknowledgement of his rights. In the
situations in which the dialectic of the reciprocal acknowledgement among
citizens as human beings, with equal rights, becomes impossible, with the risk
of the destruction of the moral order, the offender, in so far as he declares
himself an outlaw, must be condemned to live outside of human society, either
being expelled to live in the jungle or in the not colonized lands. Only when
this is not possible, as it still was in the nineteenth century, the death
penalty is exceptionally justified. But then, according to Fichte, there is no
proper penalty, but shame, for we are not talking any more of an individual but
of a social enemy, a parasite. This way society treats the criminal with his
own law, the law of the jungle.
Fichte
was always a defender of the rational political principles that had arisen in
the French Revolution, but he opposed Napoleon when he invaded Prussia in the
sense that he did not represent the expansion of the French Revolution, but
rather its involution to feudal despotism. In this he agrees with Auguste
Comte, who saw Napoleon, in his attempt to restore Imperial Monarchy, like
Julian the Apostate who aimed to restore paganism against Christianity,
opposing to the general progress that which was civilizing. Unlike Hegel, who
saw in Napoleon the incarnation of the universal spirit, Fichte proposed his
destruction. For this reason he fought against him courageously in his Address
to the German Nation (1808) pronounced in front of a crowded auditory in
the Academy of Sciences in Berlin, under the occupation of the Napoleonic
troops.
The
revolutionary France, as the civilizing torchbearer, had failed and Germany had
to take over, according to Fichte. This was a surprising claim, for at that
moment Germany was not more that a decadent aggregate of small principalities
resulting of the decadence and fragmentation of the Holy Roman Empire. Germany
had been, as Fichte points out in his famous Address, the origin of
European civilization, mixing the Christian of Roman origin with the ancestral
traditions of the Germanic people. However, during Kant´s time, Fichte saw that
the Germans started to show certain traits of cultural supremacy in Europe. For
this reason Germany would be, once its unification as a modern and democratic
nation had been done, Humanity´s new civilizing engine, after France.
Nevertheless, Fichte remains cautious, warning his people that, if Germany
failed, the only one who could take over was the country which according to the
democrats of the time could harbor such hope and avoid a regression to
political despotism: the USA. In such a sense Fichte's political ideas are
those of a democratic reformer, far from the political totalitarianisms with
which he is usually related.
Fichte's
philosophy produced a great impact during his time. Friedrich Schlegel said
that the three most important events during his time had been the French
Revolution, Fichte's philosophy and Goethe's Wilhelm Meister. He was a
very deep philosopher and, although Hegel and Schelling understood what was
essential to his philosophy in Jena, they ignored great part of his later
evolution offered in his courses of the University of Berlin. University known
as “Humboldt”, which he himself contributed to found and of which he was the
first Rector. He died on the 29th of January of 1814 from a virus
transmitted by his wife, Johanna Maria Rahn, niece of the poet Klopstock, which
she got during her service as a volunteer nurse in the War of Liberation of
Prussia from the Napoleonic occupation.
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario