After having emphasized in a
comparative analysis between the Greco-Roman Hellenistic philosophical world
and Contemporary Philosophy, in a previous article with the same title, that
Stoicism had been the philosophical movement of greatest influence and
importance in the ideological unification which occurred at the end of the
Roman Empire with Constantine's triumphant Christianity, and that a similar
functional role, in the globalizing ideological tendency which seems to start
to impose itself in the most advanced democracies of the world, could
correspond in Western thought, under the North American supremacy, to a renewed
positivist philosophy, we will try to complement such analysis with the
consideration of the role, likewise positive, although less fundamental, that
the contributions of the other great Hellenistic philosophical school had, that
of the Epicureans, in the configuration of that resulting new religious
ideological conception which was the mentality or way of understanding and
giving sense to the world of medieval Christianity. And this, in relation to
the humanistic ideological virtual unification, not anymore theist monotheist,
that is beginning to powerfully crystallize in Western societies under the
aegis of North America.
Regarding Epicureanism we must
point out that its initial failure is usually situated around the second
century AD, in which the number of followers of such doctrine, spread through a
vast number of Hellenistic cities, remarkably diminishes at the same time that
the number of Christians considerably increases in an unstoppable manner: “[The
Church] had by the end of the second century become a much stronger and
influential organism than Epicureanism had ever been” (B. Farrington, The
faith of Epicurus, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London, 1967, p. 146). Later
the Epicurean movement would completely disappear after the Edict of the
emperor Constantine which legalized the Christians, their direct competitors,
converting to Christianity even many of its followers. The Christian movement,
which had taken the Idea of Equality of the human genre from the Stoics,
especially took, nevertheless, from the Epicureans the way of organizing the
basic communities sustained in the personal relationship of fraternity, very
similar to the friendship which grounded the communes or “gardens” founded by
Epicurus, following the model of the Garden in Athens. The forthcoming
monastical medieval life, especially in the conventual Cistercian version,
follows this model of organization, in a functional comparative sense similar
to the one which also sustains the similarity between the first Christian
hermits, who went to live to the desert (the film Simon of the Desert by
Luis Buñuel is a humorous reconstruction of those anchorites) despising the
comfortable life of the polis, and the Athenian Cynic philosophers who intended
to live a more authentic and wise life dispensing of the superfluous citizen
comforts.
Furthermore, Christians imitated
also the propagandistic techniques created by Epicurus: “In the Christian era
before the age of Constantine Epicureans and Christians had much in common.
Their method of propaganda, by word of mouth; and their method of holding their
scattered communities together, by an epistolary literature were common to
both; and since Epicureans were the earlier in the field by three centuries the
pattern was probably of their making. Both communities faced the problem of the
style to be employed in addressing themselves to a wide public. Epicurus tried
to use words in their ordinary acceptation. Cicero complained that the Latin
popularizers of Epicureanism wrote in a uncultivated style. The Christian
Fathers, in order to be understood by all often avoided the politer forms of
speech” (B. Farrington, op.cit., p. 144-5). Christianity incorporates such
organizational techniques with Saint Paul. For this reason, it is not
accidental that the main works of Epicurus are the letters to Menoeceus, to
Pythocles, to the friends of Lampsacus, to the friends of Egypt, etc., and
those of Saint Paul are the epistle to the Corinthians, to the Galatians, to
Philemon, to Timothy, etc.
Moreover, the Epicureans in
contrast to the Stoics summed up the essential of their philosophy in a simple
and easy to understand book, the Tetrapharmakos, used regularly in the teaching
of the catechumens, women and men of any age, just as the Christians will do
secularly with their catechesis: “Pupils could be male or female, old or young,
even children were admitted, but not all were resident. Resident adults were
called fellow-students in philosophy; elementary classes were taken all day
long in any available corner of the garden. The pupils were said to be 'in
course of preparation', for which the Greek term was kataskeuazomenoi, a
forerunner of the Christian term catechumens” (B. Farrington, op.cit.,
p. 126). It is true that Epicureans and Christians differed philosophically,
for the former were supporters of an atomistic materialism and the latter were
creationist spiritualists. However, they agreed in two essential things: to
overcome the fear of arbitrary pagan gods and not to fear death; although for
different causes, the former basing themselves in pure reason and the latter in
a new faith which strengthened itself relying on the Skeptic school's constant
and increasing criticism of knowledge, both empirical and rational, of Stoics
and Epicureans, from Pyrrho to Aenesidemus or Sextus Empiricus. For this
reason, Skepticism was also incorporated to the ultimate Christian synthesis,
insofar as it was critical and undermining of the rational dogmatism of such
schools.
Accordingly Epicureanism, despite
its failure as an alternative and radical movement of social change in the mid
and long term, contributed with many aspects in its way of understanding
philosophy to the constitution of the ultimate ideological synthesis of the
Roman Empire which makes its way with the uprising of Christianity, not only as
a mere official religion that substitutes pagan polytheism, but as something
more important, as a new “spiritual power”, as Auguste Comte would say, of the
so-called medieval organic society that finally substitutes the constantly
ideologically divided, along its creative although also troubled and insecure
existence, Greco-Roman society.
Such a comparative analysis leads
us to think that the humanist positivist philosophy which has its origin in
Auguste Comte, and that has succeeded in the USA against its Marxist rival or
other less influential European philosophical movements, such as Nietzschean
Vitalism or Existentialism, will not monopolize in the future, in the form of a
Pensée Unique, the great synthesis of a sort of Comtean Religion of
Humanity which seems to be breaking its way in the ideological horizon of the
most industrialized countries. For many aspects of ideological organization,
techniques of propaganda of a philosophy for everybody and not only for an
elite of scientists and sages, moral aspects, etc., will surely be conserved,
taken and imitated from the work of a great thinker as Marx. For, just as the
great Epicurus made serious mistakes in his Physics when he claimed against
Democritus the necessity of granting freedom to the atoms (the clinamen)
in order to explain the formation of the Cosmos (granting a sort of freedom to
the atoms or to the electrons would make many physicist laugh nowadays), we
could seriously consider that also Marx made a mistake, e.g., in his scientific
economic assumption of the existence of a surplus value that was taken from the
worker to explain the value of the produced commodities. The rival theory of
economics, Marginalism, explains much better and with a great mathematical
precision the value that a commodity should have without resorting to such
hypotheses of an alienation of value. Nonetheless, other aspects of the Marxist
philosophy such as its insistence on the realization (Verwirklichung) of
Philosophy in practical life, on extending philosophy to general education and
popularizing it with that sort of Tetrapharmakos that is the Communist
Manifesto, although with other contents, will surely persist and be necessary
in order to configure the global ideological synthesis toward which we seem to
move in the Western World. The so-called movement of the Indignados (the Outraged), the protest against the new economical and social abuses that appear
in the stage of a global scale industrialization, will surely be motives enough
for new ideological movements that will need to use many of those philosophical
aspects which will be conserved as philosophical acquisitions and remain in the
future. For this reason, we can conclude by saying that in the struggle of the
main movements in Contemporary Philosophy, just as it happened in Hellenistic
Philosophy, although in different measure, all of them will have something
essential to contribute in the configuration of the Future Globalized Society
that seems to be reserved to the inhabitants of planet Earth and that so many
futurist series have begun to depict in the contemporary social imaginary.
Manuel F. Lorenzo
(Translated into English by Luis Fernández Pontón)
Manuel F. Lorenzo
(Translated into English by Luis Fernández Pontón)
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario