The first decade of the ongoing century has
marked a change in the so-called “philosophy of mind” - of great interest in
the USA and, because of the mighty North American influence on cultural
tendencies, in the rest of the world- that we could denominate the “return to
Husserl”, parodying the famous “return to Kant” (Zurück zu Kant) which
took place in the second half of the 19th century in the German philosophy.
After decades of an overwhelming predominance of analytic philosophy in that
country, headed by the charismatic figure of Wittgenstein, very significant
winds of change seem to blow. The cause for these changes is in the great
development experienced by the so-called “cognitive sciences” in the last
decades of the past century, especially in the 90's, known as the “Brain's
Decade” because of the appearance of new technologies, such as scanners, that
allow advances in neurophysiology with important findings in regard to the
explanation of neurological cognitive processes. Results that converge with
others provided by robotics and the Artificial Intelligence, genetics,
psycholinguistics, evolutive psychology, paleoanthropology, etc., making
positive scientific knowledge about human knowledge advance considerably and,
what matters to us more here, causing the revision of philosophies of knowledge
such as logical positivism, which underlies the analytical tradition of
Anglo-Saxon predominance.
The influent book of two of the proponents of
cognitive sciences in Linguistics, Lakoff & Johnson, Philosophy in the
flesh (1999), referred to Merleau-Ponty in their search for help to renew
the North American Philosophy setting it free from its dogmas proceeding from
English logical empiricism and bringing it closer to the phenomenological
tradition of the so-called European “Continental Philosophy” proceeding from
Husserl. Lakoff & Johnson proposed to treat the problems of the philosophy
of the “mind” in relation to the bodily actions of subjects as a key to their
interpretation. This way, the important activity of thought had to be referred,
more than to sensations, to the bodily actions of the subjects in their
semantic interpretation. This new point of view was named embodied mind
and it is causing a kind of paradigm change in the field of the so-called
philosophy of mind that accompanies the advances of the cognitive sciences. At
the same time this seems to lead to a renewal or refoundation of the positivist
philosophy's tradition so influent in the USA, as we have been claiming in
another previous article in this blog (“For a refoundation of the positivist Philosophy”, 21-11-2012). Through a graduate student of mine who had
gone to the University of Barcelona to take part in a Master, José Luis Nuño
Viejo, prematurely deceased in tragic circumstances, I had news of the E.
Thompson's book, Mind in Life. Biology, phenomenology and the sciences of mind
(2007), which he especially recommended to me because he saw similarities
between this author and the line of philosophical investigation denominated Pensamiento Hábil
that I was developing and that he knew from my lectures and some articles that
I had published by that time. The lecture of Thompson's book brought to my
knowledge this philosophy of the embodied mind, that I had already seen
applied to linguistic issues in Lakoff, now applied to biological science's
problems, as well as informing me about a broad literature prominent in this
new tendency denominated “enactive view”.
However, what most interested me immediately
was the bibliographical reference, in Husserl's interpretations, to a young
Danish philosopher called Dan Zahavi, who is playing an important role, because
of his international effect, inside this return to Husserl. The interest woken
up by this philosopher deserves a more detailed consideration, for it was hard
20 or 30 years ago to predict that Husserl's work was going to arouse again
such a strong attraction. A complicated work and difficult to know, because the
great part of what he wrote was not published in life of the philosopher,
remaining in the Husserl Archive of the University of Louvain, after its
bewildering withdrawal from Nazi Germany carried out by the Catholic priest Van
Breda. Zahavi recognizes in an interview that when he decided to orient his
academic career dedicating his doctoral works to Husserl, his decision was seen
then as something out of place because of its outdatedness. However his study
of Husserl was not merely historical-philological, but shared with his interest
for the so-called “Cognitive Sciences”. From this resulted an unexpected
connection because of which new views in such sciences rose, like the embodied
mind, which began to break the monopoly that the computationalist psychology
held for three decades in the explanation of the Mind, or like the new
technologies of brain images obtained with scanners in neuroscience. Such
views, from the 90's to today, have encouraged the re-discovery of the
phenomenology of the late Husserl and of Merleau-Ponty, who was a pioneer in
his study as a deeper and more adequate philosophy as logical empiricism,
predominant until recently because of the overwhelming influence of
Wittgenstein and his analytical followers. This way, names of scientists and
philosophers who return to phenomenological views, such as F. Varela, Evan
Thompson, Eleanor Rosch, Andy Clark, Shaun Gallagher, etc., have begun to
arouse interest. Zahavi has published two books with great success: Husserl´s
Phenomenology (2003) and, in collaboration with Shaun Gallagher, The
phenomenological Mind. An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive
Science (2008). He also directs the Center for Subjectivity Research
in the University of Copenhagen.
It doesn't seem to be one philosophical fashion
more, rather it seems that his interest for Husserl and his present growing
prestige in the field of cognitive sciences, where a dialogue and an
international discussion between philosophers and scientists still exists while
it has been lost in other fields, have more to do with the confirmation that
the results achieved by such sciences give to the greater suitability of
“phenomenological” positivism than to that one held until now by “logical”
positivism, to interpret their brilliant and innovative experimental results.
In a similar way to how the Mediterranean diet, typical among South European
countries, less developed than those from the North, imposes itself, however,
among the taste of consumers not only for a mere and arguable reason of taste,
but because it is more suitable to health as the medical-biological
investigation confirms. What we miss in this philosophical approach to
cognitive themes, especially to the psychological, is that it is not noticed
that also phenomenology – really the last contemporary philosophical paradigm
comparable to what in the 19th century was the Idealist paradigm opened by
Kant, as I have presented in my book Del Yo al Cuerpo (2011) – can be
overcome by a new philosophical movement that reaches what the last Husserl
seemed to pretend, the step from a phenomenology of “essences” or static
structures to a dynamic, operational and genetic phenomenology. I believe that
Piaget's work, known and sometimes quoted by such authors, can help to open a
path or a, to say it in a Hegelian way, preservation-overcoming of the
phenomenology. In such sense we have proposed the path or method that we call Operatiológico
(see in this Blog: “Fenomenología y Operatología” 8-8-2011 and 9-1-2012).
Manuel F. Lorenzo
(Translate into English by Luis Fernández Pontón)
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario