The
origin of Contemporary Philosophy is usually situated in a series of
philosophical movements that agree in opposing in an innovative way to Hegel's
philosophy. The young Marx considered Hegel as a sort of Aristotle of Modern
Philosophy (see in this blog, “Hegel y Aristóteles”) who opened a new age in
the development of philosophy similar to that of the hellenistic philosophical
schools that came after Aristotle with the Epicureans, Stoics, Skeptics, etc.
Schools that will not be now merely Schools of Knowledge, as the Platonic
Academy and the Aristotelean Lyceum basically were, but Schools of Salvation,
in the sense that in them knowledge is subordinated to the saving action of the
individuals. This is why in such new schools supreme knowledge was practical
knowledge, Ethics.
We
can, this way, following Marx's indication, generalize such comparison between
the third century before Christ and the nineteenth century. Accordingly,
Marxism would be a philosophical movement alternative to modern society, just
as Epicurism wanted to be alternative to the Antique society. Marx himself in
his beginnings took his admired Epicurus as a model, who he saw as a precursor
of enlightened critique to religion and as the creator of a philosophical
movement that advocated an alternative lifestyle to that one of the society of
his time, getting to have a lot of followers scattered over the Greek and Roman
cities (the lecture of Benjamin Farrington's book, The Faith of Epicurus,
Littlehampton Book Services Ltd, 1967, is very illustrative in this regard). We
can say, thus, that Marxism is a sort of modern Epicureanism in which the
friendship that united the Epicurean communes is substituted by the worker's
fraternity in the fight for an alternative to the society of their time. This
society would show itself as utopian, since Epicureanism began to loose
strength as a social movement around the 2nd century AD and Marxism
after the fall of the Berlin Wall. This was not foreign to the successful
performance in the transformation of society of an opposite philosophical
tendency, as was Stoicism in the ancient world and Positivism in the modern.
Because if Epicureanism and Marxism set the goal of their efforts in the
achievement of a happy life, of a paradise on Earth, Stoicism sets its
principal objective in the triumph of the Virtue that would enable to reform
from the inside the political society really existent and the Positivism in the
Comtean combination of Order with Progress, renouncing alternative utopias that
promise a purely illusory world. Hence, Marxism and Positivism are so different
philosophies and so opposite as Epicureans and Stoics were in ancient times.
Nevertheless,
both Epicureans and Stoics had in common their strong commitment to human
rationality as a sound instrument of truth knowledge and guide in life. They
were considered “dogmatic” philosophies in the sense that they rested on
rational principles in consistency with which they deployed their philosophical
statements, which were taken to be wise. A school had risen against this
strongly rationalist position that would eventually undermine it and subject it
to a devastating critique: the Skeptic School founded by Pyrrho. It is in the
time of Arcesilaus and Carneades, well advanced the Hellenistic period, when
Skepticism achieves quite a success in his fight against the weakest aspects of
Stoicism, e.g., the astrologic beliefs. Furthermore, Skepticism reaches a new
form of ataraxia or mind imperturbability with the discovery of the
impossibility to attain absolutely true knowledge and the conformity with
knowing the merely probable. Such critiques influenced the renewal of Stoicism
undertaken by the so-called “Middle Stoa”, by Panaetius of Rhodes, who develops
a critical Stoicism, rejecting, for example, the astrology and its inexorable
predictions of the future, and recovering the classic Platonic legacy taken by
the founder Zeno, commencing in this way a transcendental renewal because of
its later influence in the Roman Stoicism following Seneca and Marcus Aurelius.
Epicureanism suffered, without being able to renew itself, the skeptical
criticism, practically disappearing in the 2nd century AD. This was
due also to the success of the Stoicism renewed during the rationalization of
the Roman Empire at the time of the great emperors of the 2nd
century, when it became an official ideology (see Renan's book, Marcus
Aurelius and the End of Ancient World, Ulan Press, 2012).
The
equivalent of the critical function that skepticism carries out regarding
Epicureans and Stoics is, we think, in contemporary philosophy Schopenhauer's
and Nietzsche's Vitalism, in the sense that its main critical strength is aimed
against a fundamental belief common to both Positivism and Marxism: the belief
in historical Progress. The idea of the Eternal Return that Nietzsche
associates with his Zarathustra allow him to introduce the possibility of
overcoming progressivist humanism, outlining the figure of an ultra-human
beyond, in an overcoming of the ideologies of Modernity, that proclaims the
Irrationalism of life, of Nature as Will, against History. Nietzsche's
influence opened the possibility of new forms of positive philosophy, such as
those engendered in Husserl's Phenomenological Movement (who went so far as to
say ¨We are the true positivists¨), specially in Max Scheler and Heidegger or
Ortega y Gasset. At the same time, it caused a political reaction against Marxism which
took to the Second World War and the following Cold War. After the fall of the
Berlin Wall the lose of influence of Marxism starts to be perceived, as well as
the need to limit the development defended by the dominant positivistic
philosophies of Order and Progress, because of biological, ecological,
climatic, population factors, etc. It appears too clearly in the global
political horizon the supremacy of the new Rome, the USA, where positivistic
philosophy is today the most influential compared to Marxism or Nietzschean
Irrationalism, although it seems that a deep renewal of such Positivism can be
discerned in George Lakoff's and his follower's work, who are inspired in
Husserl's later phenomenology of the Lifeworld, as a key to explain cognitive
processes.
However
we don't believe that Phenomenology yet represents the appropriate
philosophical movement for the revitalization of Positivism, today in crisis
due to the degenerative specialism to which the Analytic Philosophy has driven
philosophy. It seems to us that the overcoming of Husserl's or Merleau-Ponty's
phenomenological Positivism is possible through an operatiological Positivism
that incorporates in a philosophical manner the renewal of the theorization of
human knowledge introduced by Piaget in the picture of the so-called “Cognitive
Sciences” of the second half of the 20th century. In this direction
we have proposed some basic approaches in the book “Introducción al
PensamientoHábil” (2007).
Manuel F. Lorenzo
(Translated into English by Luis Fernández Pontón)
"The Hellenistic Philosophical Schools and Contemporary Philosophy (II)"Manuel F. Lorenzo
(Translated into English by Luis Fernández Pontón)
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario